April 20, 2024
Casa del Fascio in Como, Italy

Escaping Post-Sellarsian Marxism’s Transcategorial Maze – Part I

Due to spatial constraints, the foregoing essay will be published in two installments.—Ed.

Introduction

For picturings to picture the pictureds; at the very least, for descriptions to index the world, the framework of picturing or the descriptive language of the sciences have to be committed to a worldly ontological complexity, causal uniformity, or an immutable1 “dimension of givenness that is not in dispute.”2 However, the dubious presupposition of causal uniformity, ontological form, or a processual reality as the differentia of the world is not an accidental but a necessary requirement for any picturing or description. While not only more overdrawn than any instance of picturing or description could instantiate, such presupposition is also in tension with Sellars’s counterpart theory of conceptual role semantics in which categories are construed as metalinguistic sortals. 

This paper will argue that transfecting the world with the categories of causal uniformity, de re modality, and real patterns as relational-structural registers of self-constituted presences of the ontological order and difference of the world, commits us to Platonistic transcendental structures, Aristotelian categories or ontological forms—an ontological preformationism or categorial realism. Sellars commits himself to two distinct varieties of transcendental invariants or categorial structures: ontological forms and nature-non-neutral existence, both viewed as trans-framework categories above and beyond any functional role that could be ascribed to them. 

The second part of this investigation will mediate the polemic between Alfred SohnRethel’s conception of real abstraction and some form of Sellarsian “social pragmatic functionalism” without assuming the former has fallen prey to the myth of the Given—as the slayer of the Given is already committed to the genus of “categorial forms,” of which “real abstraction” is the most benign species. Furthermore, the claim about the transmission of abstraction from the act of exchange to the mind in the practice of exchange can be seen as the naive pathos of any reifying cosmization, one that plagues not only Sohn-Rethel`s philosophy but also that of  many Sellarsians, as we will see below. 

It will be suggested that this can be avoided through a resolute reconceptualization of the conceptual form in terms of a new Hegelian-Brandomian account, in which conceptual contentfulness is redefined by a non-psychological-cum-non-linguistic account. The paper’s dénouement takes a pan-relationalist shape with an anti-descriptivist, expressivist heart.  

1. A Desperate Humean’s Attempt

It is no news that Copernican-inspired scientific deanthropocentrization has led to a gradual disenchantment in which all ‘levels’ of reality are purged of meaning and order in a piecemeal yet circumspect manner. The upshot of this radical suppression of meaning, order, and difference is a fatal complacency with a teleological necroptosis 3 for which the world is nothing but an “ineffable lump, devoid of structure or order.” 4 In this guise, the scientific mind bows to the inevitable and ultimately vacates its ordered and meaningful constructions to nihility. However, this classical Humean perspective seems to be impervious to a fundamental paradox. Namely, the mind—itself a part of this structureless lump as something that “goes on in nature, in itself meaninglessly,”5 rendering the last intracranial sparkles of order, meaning and difference perversely vacuous, and virtually flattening its every kinematic and dynamic parameter. The upshot of this second conceptual contraption—the transposition of worldly unstructuredness onto the mind—is a compulsive immanent critique of reason in which the ostensible necessities of the mind are exposed as contingent superfluities; a primordial indeterminacy’s reign of structural nihilism beckons.

Kant rejected this rapacious evacuation of the mind’s substantive structures and provided elaborate transcendental machinery in order to save it from Humean claws and heal its ontological fracture. Nevertheless, this remedial approach proved too high a price. Kant’s gallant but doomed engagement resulted in a duplicity of problematic consequences that any minimally ‘sane naturalism’ would find inscrutable: by “conceiv[ing] the meaning-yielding operation of mind transcendentally rather than as a part of nature,”6 Kant falls prey to a mythopoetic supernatural account with a concomitant volte-face approach that reversed the classical conceptions of the mind-world and moved from a self-sufficiently subsistent reality to a world-constituting or world-constructing mental capacity. The mind now tenaciously seizes upon all necessary order, difference, relation and structure, to the detriment of an unknowable noumenon. But how can the mind monopolize all necessity and order while “frictionless[ly] spinning in [its] void,”7 yet claim to know something, anything (structured) beyond its purview? McDowell argues that Kant’s transcendental idealism is nothing more than an attempt of “a desperate reactionary”8 to carry out the impossible: to save the ostensibly structured mind in a structureless universe. 

How does Sellars’s sophisticated philosophical machinery—for our purposes, his conception of picturing and description—fit into this debate? A perusal of Sellarsian philosophical tour de force against the background of four licit distinctions (the order of knowing: the order of justification and the order of explanation, and the order of being: ontological forms and nature-non-neutrality) will play a pivotal role in the arc of this journey. In 1981’s “Mental Events”9 Sellars thickens up his methodological wherewithal—as a stepwise unfolding of his tools—and makes a battery of valuable distinctions by “highlight[ing] the methodological point that in the domain of the mental, language is primary in the order of knowing.” 10 The priority-of-language thesis is perhaps the most significant philosophical achievement within the confines of the analytic Linguistic Turn for Sellars: It is meant to underwrite a substantial level of epistemic disunity between the binary dialectic of being—whether mental or material—and language. That is to say: any conceptual thought or activity whatsoever about any “level” of reality will depend on the mastery of language.11 Furthermore, the overall upshot of the linguistic priority thesis is the semantic liquidation of the problematic pantheon of meaning, order, and difference (morals, modals, mathematicals, and mentals) and a sapping of the foundation of any object-naturalist/realist camp “given a linguistic conception of the origin of [these] problems,”12 

This thoroughgoing linguistic liquidation of semantic discourse is called the “negative thesis” because it proscribes the relevant bits of the problematic language from invading illegitimate territories: “[morals, modals, mathematicals, and mentals are not] descriptive’, ‘truth-apt’, ‘fact-stating’, ‘propositional’, ‘representational’, or something of that kind.”13 Not only the ostensible pantheons of meaning and order should be investigated according to an anthropological-linguistic or subject-naturalist perspective, but also the descriptive vocabulary of the sciences is put on a par with them, hence rejecting the alleged “bifurcation” that separates the descriptive and the non-descriptive segments of language.14

Rejection of this bifurcated or dimorphic conception of linguistic practice propitiates a “metaconceptual approach to the nature of ontological categories […] to interpret and reconstruct [them] in terms of […] ‘meaning as use’ or norm governed inferential role semantics,”15 for which meaningfulness requires no “meanings” and conceptual contents of any segment of language need no cartography of ontological truth-makers or falsity-makers, traditionally purported to give content to thinking and acting—the positive thesis. This ingenious transposition of “meaning” as “use” compels us to “construe […] universals, propositions, and other ‘metaphysical’ constructions as reifications of conceptual norms, and thus as representations of the very forces – i.e., institutionally upheld canons of correctness – to which the pragmatist grants primacy.”16

Linguistic functional role deflation of causal/modal “meaning” is called causal/modal expressivism because it defines causal categories and modal contentfulness as operated by non-descriptive metalinguistic sortals, prescriptive reifications of norms, non-empirical framework-explicitating devices, or something of that sort. This version of expressivism leads to another, new version of ontological structural nihilism: in it, causality and modality transmigrate from reality to humanity, or to linguistic practices. The impetus behind this causal/modal expressivism, as I understand it, is the erasure and abatement of the misbegotten idea of the “Given”—namely, “the idea that the space of reasons, the space of justifications or warrants, extends more widely than the conceptual sphere.”17 That is to say, the critique of the myth of the Given implies an epistemic or justificatory conceptualism in which only concepts (or concepts-like items) or conceptually structured items can play the irreducible epistemic roles of justification and warrant in bearing on our rational adjustments to the world. The conceptual sphere, prima facie, includes the menagerie of shared human comportments residing within the space of reason and warrant—including the causal vocabulary we use to justify our causal claims and describe/explain the causal/modal transactions that we happen to engage in and with the world. This, however, seems quite anachronistic: causal transactions and explanations of those are not the targets of the Myth of Given—its aim is at their justification

By decoupling the order of justification from the order of explanation,18 we thereby avoid the conflation of causal claims acting as truth-makers and causal claims as posits within the descriptive vocabulary and explanatory resources of the sciences. The potential for causal explanations to be inherent in causal language is precipitated only with this distinction within the order of knowing or signification itself. The reason why Sellars thinks this distinction is an intra-signification distinction is multifaceted, but basically boils down to a two-stage argumentative strategy of firstly juxtaposing description and explanation: “The descriptive and explanatory resources of language advance hand in hand”;19 and then explicating explanations (and specifically causal/modal explanations) as shadows of norms, normative commitments, and linguistic correctness. It is therefore important to realize that the presence in the object language of the causal modalities (and of the logical modalities and of the deontic modalities) serves not only to express existing commitments, but also to provide the framework for the thinking by which we reason our way (in a manner appropriate to the specific subject matter) into the making of new commitments and the abandoning of old. 20

The overall upshot of this is that counterfactual dispositions and causal modalities, or the specific linguistic tributary we use to express the “iffyness,” as Sellars calls them,21 are “shadows cast by the norms themselves.”22 Hence causal modalities are repatriated to their original niche by making functional-role linguistic correctness or incorrectness their truth-makers or falsity-makers: “language of modality is […] transposed language of norms.”23

If this causal/modal expressivism with its premise of meaning-use functional role semantics is correct, then how can we “defend […] a domain-specific, naturalistic […] causal theory of empirical reference and of representational correspondence to the world (or ‘picturing’)’?24 Since this use-theoretic approach to meaning and content of causal/modal claims seems to be in continually entangled relations with a deflationary stance towards ontological commitments about causal/modal claims, then it is a far cry from any avowed realist ontology that purports a mind-independent reality.25 This meritorious recognition of an absolute functional similitude between the descriptive (categorial/causal/modal) ontological language and the expressivist use for the ostensible pantheons of meaning, order, and difference, leads to an unvarying creed of deflationism about categories and specifically of causal categories which would turn out to be of paramount importance for any purportedly non-signifying picturing relation between mind and world, or even for any natural-scientific descriptiveness überhaupt.

A Sellarsian order of being would be a minimal yet positive characterization of beingTo disentangle being from its order, we need to distinguish between two ontological categories: ontological form and nature-non-neutrality. Ontological form “is not the form of symbols, but the form of entitieswhich may be represented by symbols in virtue of their form (the structure of such representation being the purview of semantics).”26 Form is usually understood as the relational “manner” in which an entity x exists: “[…] as numerically distinct from yexists as ontologically dependent on yexists as a whole of and and exists as a proper part of y.”27 For Sellars, the ontological form will amount to the episodic “uniformities.”  Specifically, causal/modal uniformities extant within the scheme of things. In this vein, causality and modality will signal reality. Causal-relational uniformity will do so for the order of actuality. 

This is the centralizing assumption: There must be certain uniformities in sets of natural objects that can be viewed as an isomorphism between two sets of such natural objects.28 Once we adopt the causal framework, we can embrace the ontological (form of the causal) uniformity in the order of being. However, to assume this “Axiom of Uniformity” is to commit oneself to the unquestionable assumption of a univocal ontology “that some one basic pattern pervades the universe”;29 that “[at] the ultimate level, the universe has a common structure throughout.”30 Yet these causal uniformities and patterns are the real ontological categories that need to be at least one step removed from any conceptual articulation or predicative determination of both the cognitive-theoretical-descriptive permutations and the prescriptive-normative variations that are the bread and butter of conceptual role semantics. Hence in the order of being, there is no liberation from the manacles of a preconceptually fixed common structure of an ontologically real kind. This order is the true Sellarsian “Ariadne’s thread to the labyrinth of [the pictured or described world.]”31 Furthermore, nomos, nomological statements, counterfactual dispositions, and law-like generalizations like “all A’s are B’s,” which index the very ordered furniture of the world are semantically derivative of an inference or rulea rule that takes us from A-claims to B-claims, or licenses us inferentially in an unidirectional way. That is to say, nomological permutations between states of affairs and counterfactual transmutations amongst properties make sense to us only by virtue of the role they play in inference and explanation. Hence even natural nomos becomes the shadow and reification of norms: “[W]here the object language does not permit us to say ‘If a were f, it would be y’ we can achieve the same purpose by saying[:] ‘ya’ may be inferred from ‘fa’.”32

To opt for an ordered being is to be causally/modally relationalist-structuralist in one’s ontological commitments, and to posit the pictured or the described world in terms of a causal isomorphic realism. For picturings to be isomorphic to the pictureds or describings to be isomorphic to the describables, both relata must be permeated with an ontological form and be construed as ordered-cum-differentiated ensembles. Hence, any picturing or description of reality will always be in tension with any version of ontological structural nihilism implied by the  conceptual role semantics sketched aboveas it is inconceivable to picture or describe a recalcitrant primordial indeterminateness. Therefore, for any picturing or descriptions of the world to hold, we have to presuppose a dialectical, formal-ontological character of natural processes in terms of causal patterns and nomological modal relations. 

However, these causal patterns and nomological modal relations would not count as conceptual framework-relative categories: For any Sellarsian “picturing” or scientific description to be instantiated, we have to assume the manner of a transcategorial/ontological form of relationality that purportedly pervades the universe; the relation being “an actual relationan empirical relation between two relational systems in the natural world.”33 But if the Sellarsian dictum of conceptual role semantics prohibits such framework-transcendence of causal uniformities—namely, if every category, including the category of episodic causal uniformity, ontological form, and nomological modal patterns is “[..] essentially classificatory, a matter of classifying conceptual items,”34, then we have to reverse the often-hailed Sellarsian methodological principle that “transcendental structures must be realized in causal structures.”35 That is to say, the reversal of this methodological principle of the framework-transcendence of causal uniformities is to put the transcendental cart before the causal horse. That is exactly what O’Shea does, as he argues the Sellarsian categories of categorial ontology such as causality, which on “Sellars’s view […] is clearly a conceptual framework-relative notion.”36 This renders the uniformitarian model of causal relations, ontological form and nomological modal patterns as secondary excrescences that need to be reflected in the uniformities of the transcendental projectand not vice versa, as the aforementioned Sellarsian methodological principle enjoins. 

Thirdly, Sellars has a further transcategorial ontological premise at his disposal that does not acquiesce to conceptual framework-relativity: a nature-non-neutral conception of being. If “nature-neutrality is neutrality on, or indifference to, the non-relational character of entities,”37 then Sellars’s distinction between “existing simpliciter” and “existing as represented38 seems to be parasitic upon a nature-non-neutral conception that grants an independent hegemony to a being that is relentlessly prior to any ”-ing/-ed” distinctions. That is to say, being’s existence is not only not conceptual framework-relative, but also transcendent to the pictured or represented or described itself. Given this thesis, it is evident that this version of realism as an ineluctable ontological commitment is even ruthlessly anterior to the causal uniformities, ontological form and nomological modal relations required for the picturing/pictured or describing/described relation itself. This is basically what Sellars’s particularism or ontological nominalism of pure processes amounts to, in this author’s opinion. But if “[A]ll awareness of sorts, resemblances, facts, etc., in short all awareness of abstract entities—indeed all awareness even of particulars—is a linguistic affair,”39 then how we can make sense of Sellars’s particularism or ontological nominalism apart from the mastery of language and conceptual role semantics?

In a nutshell, Sellars’s account of both picturing and description relies on a series of interpositions that starts from an ontological preformationism or categorial realism—one which is predicated on various notions such as existence simpliciter, causal uniformities, ontological forms and nomological modal patterns, and ends in normativity and the space of reasonswhile his conceptual role semantics rehearses the cascade of the following sequence in the reverse direction:


Nature-non-neutrality, Uniformities, Forms, Processes, Causality, Modality;

Picturing, Description, Causal Explanation40;

Normativity and Sociality.

 

So far we have argued that Sellars is an expressivist about causal modalities, ontological forms and counterfactual dispositions, because this homogenous treatment of all conceptual and categorical tributaries of language as functional classifications within the framework of reasons is a buffer against the Myth of the Given—that is because a naturalism that starts with categorially given registers of intelligibility or causal truth-makers would “rest […] upon a metaphysical or ‘Platonist’ conception of content that is recalcitrant to naturalistic forms of explanation” Hence in his conceptual role semantics about causal modalities, ontological forms, and counterfactual dispositions, he construes causal relations as intra-framework roles within a given causal language that we happen to adopt—roles  which are inferentially and functionally expressive locutions, rather than referential tokens or representational-descriptive denotations. However, Sellars invented a picturing relation as a desperate, reactionary attempt to save the world from the ineffable lump of structural nihilism entailed by his functional role semantics. For picturing or even description to work, we need to put categories of causal-modal-nomological uniformities, ontological form, or “existing simpliciter” particulars back into nature to instantiate worldly relations imbued with their own conditions of possibility. 

If that is correct, picturing as an ostensible disenchanting device always comes with re-enchanting and re-mythologizing presuppositions: The pictured or described world then becomes an intra-material soliloquy where matter imbued with order talks to matter in the sense of some meaning-constituting, order-constituting, and difference-constituting power. A power that, prima facie, only should belong to the order of signification or the space of reasons. The presupposition of causal-modal-nomological uniformity, ontological form, counterfactual dispositions, or “existing simpliciter” particularism is then seen as a quintessential arrogation of a mongrel Platonism, and a fatal vice of preconceptual representational picturing proponents and of descriptivists in the right-wing Sellarsian camp—because it is ultimately incompatible with inferential or conceptual role semantics.

[To be continued in Part II.Ed.]

Notes:

1. This dimension of givenness, which ensures that when we change our concepts ‘‘we do not change that [in nature] to which we are responding.’’ Johanna Seibt, “Functions between reasons and causes: On picturing,” Empiricism, Perceptual Knowledge, Normativity, and Realism, ed. Willem A. deVries (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), 247–281.
2. Wilfrid Sellars, “Foundations for a Metaphysics of Pure Process—The Carus Lectures,” Monist 64 (1981): 3–90.
3. Necroptosis is the forced “suicide” of infected cells. This is a good metaphor for any approach that is contaminated with teleological commitments and, in turn, forced to disintegrate.
4. John McDowell, Mind, Value and Reality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 178.
5. Ibid., 175.
6. Ibid.
7. John McDowell, Mind and World (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 11.
8. McDowell, Mind, Value, and Reality, 175.
9. Wilfrid Sellars, “Mental Events,” In the Space of Reasons, ed. Kevin Scharp and Robert B. Brandom (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007), 282–300.
10. Sellars, “Mental,” 282.
11. Wilfrid Sellars, “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” Science, Perception and Reality (London: Routledge, 1963; reprinted Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 1991), 160.
12. Huw Price, “Naturalism Without Representationalism,”Naturalism Without Mirrors, (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 86–190.
13. Huw Price, “Wilfrid Sellars Meets Cambridge Pragmatism,” Sellars and contemporary philosophy, ed. David Pereplyotchik and Deborah R. Barnbaum (New York: Routledge, 2017), 136.
14. Ibid.
15. James R. O’Shea, “On Sellars’s Analytic-Kantian Conception of Categories as Classifying Conceptual Roles,” Categorial Ontologies: From Realism to Eliminativism, ed. Javier Cumpa (forthcoming).
16. Robert Kraut, “Norm and Object: How Sellars Saves Metaphysics from the Pragmatist Onslaught,” Sellars and His Legacy, ed. James R. O’Shea (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 61.
17. McDowell, Mind and World, 7.
18. Kraut, “Norm and Object,” 61.
19. Wilfrid Sellars, “Counterfactuals, Dispositions, and the Causal Modalities,” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, ed. Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1957), 225–308.
20. Sellars, “Counterfactuals,” 302–03.
21. Sellars, “Foundations.”
22. Kraut, “Norm and Object.”
23. Wilfrid Sellars, “Inference and Meaning,” Mind 62 (1953): 313–38.
24. O'Shea, “On Sellars’s Analytic-Kantian Conception.”
25. Henrik Rydenfelt, “Realism without representationalism,” Synthese 198 (2021): 2901-2918, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02251-4.
26. David Woodruff Smith, “Intentionality Naturalized?,” Naturalizing Phenomenology (Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 1999), 87-90.
27. Jani Hakkarainen, Moderate Categorial Realism of a Relationist-Nominalist Sort (University of Tampere, Finland: forthcoming).
28. Seibt, “Functions.”
29. Keith Campbell, Abstract Particulars, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990) (emphasis added).
30. Ibid.
31. Wilfrid Sellars, “Towards a Theory of Predication,” How Things Are, ed. James Bogen and James McGuire (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1983), 314.
32. Sellars, “Inference,” 16.
33. Carl B. Sachs, “In Defense of Picturing: Sellars’s Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Neuroscience,” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (2019): 669-689, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9598-3.
34. Wilfrid Sellars, “Toward a Theory of the Categories,” Kant’s Transcendental Metaphysics: Sellars’ Cassirer Lectures Notes and Other Essays, ed. Jeffrey F. Sicha (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 2002), 328.
35. Willem DeVries, “Sellars vs. McDowell on the Structure of Sensory Consciousness,” Diametros 27 (2011): 61–62.
36. O'Shea, “On Sellars’s Analytic-Kantian Conception.”
37. Hakkarainen, “Moderate Categorial Realism.”
38. Wilfrid Sellars, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes, (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1992.), 36.
39. Sellars, “Empiricism,” 160 (emphasis added).
40. “In my opinion, the key to the answer is the realization that describing is internally related to explaining, in that sense of ‘explanation’ that comes to full flower in scientific explanation—in short, causal explanation. A descriptive term is one which, in its basic use, properly replaces one of the variables in the dialogue schema ‘What brought it about that x is [P]? That y is [S].’ where what is requested in a causal explanation.” - Wilfrid Sellars, “Empiricism and Abstract Entities,” The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (The Library of Living Philosophers) ed. Paul A. Schilpp (La Salle, IL: Open Court): 450–51.

More Articles from &&&

The Stirner Affair

Against Normative Morality  If amoralists are gathered in the history of philosophy, the initial catalog features two figures: Stirner and Nietzsche. The former appeared first, which has led to speculative claims of plagiarism by the latter. However, it is more appropriate to place Stirner among the individualists and hedonists, both before and during his time,… Read More »

The Problem of the Nature of Thought

Paulin Hountondji, the Beninese author who died in February and taught philosophy at the National University of Benin, was clearly aware of the magnitude and impact of politician Kwame Nkrumah, since, as he recalls in his autobiography The Struggle for Meaning, his presentation in Paris on the Ghanaian leader’s 1964 book Consciencism caused headlines for… Read More »

I Am A Philosopher

Last year—two years ago?—Cássia Siqueira tweeted: “Better Call Saul S06E07.” I was mystified, but didn’t ask her what it was about. I’d never watched the TV show. But anything Cássia wrote, wherever she wrote it, however cryptic, deserved investigation. So I watched the whole show, knowing I was looking for the meaning of her tweet.… Read More »

Good Times

This piece, initiated and commissioned by Marten Spangberg, is part of a larger project called “When The Museum is Closed” at the Musée d’Art et d’Histoire in Geneva.   All ideas are bad ideas. They are bad not insofar as they are impractical, useless, or lacking in any such respect. They are bad in that… Read More »

The Human Centipede: A View From the Art World*

In time for the opening of Art Basel on June 13 and the release of Eduarda Neves’s Minor Bestiary next month as a more recent critique of contemporary art, we are publishing Reza Negarestani’s “The Human Centipede: A View From The Artworld.” Only delivered once in lecture format at e-flux, New York, in November 2013,… Read More »

Other Endings

Found in the Hyperstition archives, “Other Endings” is the never-published preface to Reza Negarestani’s Cyclonopedia by Nick land, the controversial former Instructor of philosophy at The New Centre which in light of the author’s recent public declaration of his faith in Allah and Islam becomes more than just a premonition but an essential part of… Read More »

Also Reality and the Weight of Conjunctions

Determinant meaning within the English language exists by virtue of the glue that is conjunctions. Sticky little words like “but” and “also” join together, compartmentalize, and disjoint our speech, thoughts, social structure, and reality, in the mathematics of meaning. Even the American legal system depends upon conjunctions like “either/or” and the contrasts they create. Both… Read More »

Letter to the Washed Away

Dear Lee, I texted you earlier today about how Ava went missing during the fires. I’m going up the coast to look for her in a yacht I’ve stolen that belongs to friends of my parents who are away in the Austrian Alps until Christmas. Did you know that the term “yacht” comes from the… Read More »

Interpretation Contra Structural Reading

This article is an extension of “The Narcissist-Image,” departing from Fares Chalabi’s presentation in “Deleuzian Aesthetics.”  Much of Chalabi’s Deleuzian Aesthetics is based on a critique of interpretation, which for Chalabi, is a procedure for reading art where “this means that, and that means this,” that something like the color black points to a feeling… Read More »

Kunstwollen* Minus the Human (Painting in the Age of Machinic Will to Art)

1 Imagine describing the series of Jeff Perrott’s paintings New Construction (Pharmakon, Subject, Natural, Denatural, Door, Sublime, Red Interior, and Cosmic) to an AI or a blind person. How would you start? By listing which elements come first, and how the layers of lines in each painting are ordered? Describing an artwork is deconstructing or… Read More »

Ruangrupa: Contemporary Art or Friendship Industry?*

In the past two decades, more than in the past hundred years, authoritarian regimes have risen to power globally. Today, fascist parties are occupying seats in many countries’ governments, such as in the Israeli Knesset, the Dutch Tweede Kamer, the American Congress, and the German Bundestag. Meanwhile, the collective memory of European fascism and its… Read More »

Call the Bronze Age… they forgot their pictograms!

“In the preceding chapter we discussed the development of technoeconomic organization and the establishment of social machinery closely connected with the evolution of techniques. Here I propose to consider the evolution of a fact that emerged together with Homo sapiens in the development of anthropoids: the capacity to express thought in material symbols. (…) As… Read More »

Interferential Axiology: Excess & Disruption

What is tragic about choice is no longer fundamental if choice is no longer what establishes communication between an independent city and an independent individual as substances. —Gilbert Simondon1   Excess and disruption are different modes of systemic interferences, providing differing sets of axiological implications. This essay seeks to explore their tragic interface in the… Read More »

Here & Elsewhere, at War, & Into the Future

The Middle East continues to painfully be a primary site for the blood-drenched transformations of our planetary geopolitical system. However, about ten years ago and during another Israeli operation in Gaza, an uncanny timeliness opened an unexpected connection between global contemporary art and geopolitics in August 2014 when, following the escalation of Israel’s Gaza operations,… Read More »

Zionism Reconsidered

The seminal essay below by Hannah Arendt, spanning 15,000 words was first published in the Menorah Journal in October 1944. This work was inspired by the meeting of the World Zionist Organization’s American section in Atlantic City. This congress was notable for its assertive call for a Jewish state covering the entire territory of Palestine,… Read More »

The Dead God, A short story in two parts

Things had been getting strange at the firm, since the boss had come back from holidays. The black cape and the pile of Crowley books strewn about the office were the first clue. What was Hardeep, the Singaporean tech bro CEO, doing with all this, mused Pierre, a level 7 sales executive, en route to… Read More »

The Purist

Filipe Felizardo is a philosophy student, artist and musician from Lisbon, with an informal education in film, comics, and musical pedagogy. Currently a Researcher on Critical Philosophy at the New Centre for Research & Practice, Felizardo focuses on systematic reconceptions of learning and alienation, as understood from the workspaces of inferentialism, Marxist activity-approach, and anti-vitalism.

Retinol: A Mode of Action

“Condensed in a formula, the Technological Civilization can be characterized as the transition from ratio to generativity, from matter to process, from nature to the hybrid.” –Davor Löffler If we follow the self-avowed German Accelerationism and deep futurology of Davor Löffler (Löffler 2021), we can posit that everything is co-evolutionary and that there are no… Read More »

The Narcissist Image

In his course Deleuzian Aesthetics Fares Chalabi presents an extended typology of mutually exclusive, rigorously defined image-types, or what I like to call aesthetic structures or aesthetic logics. An image-type or aesthetic logic is a form that structures the entirety of a work of art – take, for example, the ‘series’. The logic of series,… Read More »

Sorry You Can’t Pass a Turing Test But I’m Different 

Five hundred million individuals tried to monetize their social media last year, according to a recent Linktree survey. As a lucky member of this esteemed group, I recently found myself surfing through the entrepreneurial side of TikTok, captivated by a video titled “How to make money with Chat GPT”. The clip tells you to go… Read More »

Unthought Apparitions

In this video essay, Brent Cox works through the poetry of Barbadian poet Kamau Brathwaite and his Sycorax Video Style, which he developed in the early 1980s using a Mac SE/30 and which offers myriad compelling extra-linguistic or extra-conceptual ideas in relation to citationality, literary convention, the constative/performative distinction, the temporality of neologisms, and the… Read More »

The Work of Art in the Age of Cybernetic Criticism

Walter Benjamin’s seminal 1935 essay “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction” wrestled with the effects of powerful technologies upon culture, and presaged much subsequent writing, e.g. Martin Heidegger and Italo Calvino. Here I want to consider not the artwork-qua-object as in Benjamin, but rather the work of art as an active force, in… Read More »

Modern Art: A True Conspiracy

*Originally delivered as a response to Gertrude Stein’s “The Making of Americans” on Day 27 of Superconversations, a collaboration between e-flux and The New Centre for Research & Practice in 2015. The most recent wartime Christmas in New York was as cold and bright as any other holiday season had ever been in the city. As usual, a… Read More »

Cosmotechnics & the Multicultural Trap

1. Although still a young writer and researcher, it is probably not an exaggeration to say that Yuk Hui is already one of the most influential contemporary thinkers of technology working today. This position is certainly warranted by the strength and scope of his work, the expansive drive and breadth of which is inspiring, especially… Read More »

Pandemic, Time for a Transversal Political Imagination*

I: Symptoms With the omnipresence of the term “symptom” these days, it seems that a plausible escape from the deep horror of this pandemic would be to conduct a symptomatic reading of it. Attributed to Louis Althusser, this method of reading literary and historical texts focuses not on what a text evidently expresses, but on… Read More »